Get the latest AI workflows to boost your productivity and business performance, delivered weekly by expert consultants. Enjoy step-by-step guides, weekly Q&A sessions, and full access to our AI workflow archive.
Summary
This video dives into the fascinating and complex world of mathematics, focusing on the axiom of choice and its consequences. It explores the historical struggle of mathematician Georg Cantor to order the real numbers and his development of set theory, which caused turmoil in the mathematical community. The video outlines Cantor's discoveries about different sizes of infinity, the infamous Banach-Tarski Paradox, and the controversial reactions to these findings. It concludes by discussing the axiom's usefulness and its acceptance in modern mathematics, despite its paradoxical implications.
Highlights
Georg Cantor's pursuit to order the real numbers almost drove him to madness. 🤯
Cantor's Diagonalization Proof shows that real numbers are uncountably infinite. 🔢
The Banach-Tarski Paradox demonstrates perplexing outcomes of infinite duplication. 🎩
The acceptance of the Axiom of Choice changed over time, from contestation to a staple in modern mathematics. 🔍
Key Takeaways
Georg Cantor's work revealed that not all infinities are equal, causing a stir in mathematics. 🌌
The Axiom of Choice allows for selections from infinite sets, leading to paradoxical results. 🤯
The Benach-Tarski Paradox, enabled by the Axiom of Choice, suggests infinite duplication is theoretically possible. 🪄
Math debates on the Axiom of Choice were intense, before its acceptance as a standard axiom. 📚
The Axiom of Choice is incredibly useful for simplifying proofs and making math more manageable. ✨
Overview
The video unpacks the journey of Georg Cantor, a mathematician who faced harsh criticism for his groundbreaking work on set theory and the nature of infinities. Cantor's endeavors to map the real numbers and his subsequent revelations about different sizes of infinity shook the foundations of mathematics, introducing complex philosophical debates.
Cantor's Diagonalization Proof paved the way for understanding uncountable infinities, highlighting the paradoxical nature of infinity in mathematics. The Axiom of Choice, while controversial, allows for making selections in infinite sets, resulting in puzzling phenomena like the Banach-Tarski Paradox, where a single object can theoretically be duplicated infinitely.
Despite the initial uproar, the Axiom of Choice eventually gained acceptance due to its utility in simplifying mathematical proofs. Today, it is a standard component of modern mathematics, highlighting the field’s evolution and the ongoing quest to balance logical principles with abstract concepts.
Chapters
00:00 - 00:30: Introduction to the Paradox in Mathematics This chapter introduces a mathematical rule that, while seemingly simple and intuitive, leads to paradoxical outcomes. Accepting the rule suggests the existence of line segments with no length and the ability to split a sphere into two identical spheres without adding material. Despite the paradoxes, this axiom has underpinned over a century of mathematical development. The chapter poses a foundational question on the validity of this rule, linking it to the concept of choice.
00:30 - 01:00: Choosing a Number in Math: Human vs. Mathematical Process The chapter discusses the difference between the human ability to randomly choose numbers and the mathematical process of generating numbers. It highlights that while humans can seemingly pick numbers randomly, mathematical processes follow set formulas and algorithms, leading to consistent outcomes. The chapter also touches on the concept of pseudo-random number generation in computers, which is not truly random but is based on specific algorithms, often influenced by the current time.
01:00 - 01:30: Selecting Numbers: From Rules to Real Numbers The chapter discusses the concept of selecting numbers in mathematics without the ability to choose randomly, emphasizing the necessity of following a rule. An example rule provided is always choosing the smallest number. It highlights how this rule works well with whole positive integers and prime numbers, using one and two respectively as examples. However, selecting real numbers is more complex due to the diversity in types, including positive, negative, whole, fractional, and irrational numbers like pi or the square root of two.
01:30 - 02:00: The Challenge of Ordering Real Numbers The chapter explores the complexities of ordering real numbers, emphasizing the difficulty in choosing the smallest number due to the infinite nature of real numbers. It exemplifies this by attempting to select the smallest number after one, which proves to be an endless task due to the infinite possibilities such as 1.01, 1.0001, and 1.00000000001, questioning the concept of what truly follows one.
02:00 - 02:30: Georg Cantor: The Quest to Order Real Numbers The chapter titled 'Georg Cantor: The Quest to Order Real Numbers' discusses the challenges and intrigue around ordering real numbers. It highlights the problem of specifying a sequential order for real numbers, such as next, previous, first, and last, despite having infinite options. The chapter focuses on Georg Cantor and his mission, beginning in 1870, to establish a definitive order for real numbers, a task he pursued intensely, impacting his well-being drastically.
02:30 - 03:00: Galileo's Influence on Infinity and Cantor's Challenge The chapter discusses the impact of Galileo's work on the concept of infinity and how it influenced Georg Cantor's revolutionary contributions to mathematics. Cantor faced significant controversy after publishing a paper at the age of 29 that challenged previous notions of infinity. The chapter explores the question raised by Galileo regarding whether there are more natural numbers or more square numbers, noting the increasing sparsity of square numbers at higher values.
03:00 - 03:30: Cantor's Diagonalization Proof and Countability The chapter discusses the concept of comparing the sizes of infinite sets, specifically focusing on Cantor's Diagonalization Proof and the concept of countability. An example is given using Galileo's realization that there are as many square numbers as there are natural numbers because a one-to-one correspondence can be drawn between them, challenging intuitive understanding. This leads to the conclusion that the terms "more than" or "less than" are complex when dealing with infinite sets.
03:30 - 04:00: Countable vs. Uncountable Infinities Traditionally, infinity has been perceived as a single, unending concept, encompassing the idea of 'foreverness.' This perspective remained dominant for centuries and continues to be a prevalent understanding of infinity for many. However, in 1874, mathematician Georg Cantor challenged this view. He hypothesized the possibility of two infinite sets existing that could not be perfectly mapped onto each other, suggesting the existence of different types, or sizes, of infinities.
04:00 - 04:30: Cantor's Well-Ordering Theorem Cantor embarked on a mission to compare the natural numbers with real numbers between zero and one by attempting to map them perfectly one-to-one. He envisioned creating an infinite list pairing each natural number with a real number. In this imagined list creation, the lack of a smallest real number meant the real numbers could be listed in any order he chose. Even after assuming completion of this infinite list, Cantor proposes the formation of another real number.
04:30 - 05:00: Cantor's Personal and Professional Struggles The chapter explores Cantor's struggles both in his personal life and his professional endeavors. It details a method that Cantor uses to generate a real number between zero and one, a method which involves modifying the digits of a sequence of numbers to create a new number that does not appear in the initial list, showcasing his mathematical creativity amidst his challenges.
05:00 - 05:30: Zermelo's Support and the Axiom of Choice In this chapter, the concept of Cantor's Diagonalization Proof is explored. It reveals that there are more real numbers between zero and one than there are natural numbers, by ensuring a difference in at least one digit from each number on a list. This proof demonstrates that infinity can have different sizes.
05:30 - 06:00: Formalizing the Axiom of Choice The chapter discusses different types of infinities, starting with countable infinities such as the set of square numbers, integers or rational numbers that can be paired perfectly with natural numbers. Cantor named these countable infinities. The chapter then transitions to larger infinities termed uncountable infinities, which include the set of all real numbers and complex numbers that cannot be matched one-to-one with natural numbers.
06:00 - 06:30: Demonstrating the Axiom of Choice The chapter discusses Cantor's groundbreaking work in the mathematical community. Despite criticism, he persisted in his quest to organize even uncountably infinite sets into a definitive order. He introduced the concept of a well-ordering, which required two specific conditions for a set.
06:30 - 07:00: The Vitali Set and Non-measurability In this chapter, the concept of a well-ordered set is introduced, where both the entire set and its subsets have clear starting points, ensuring a defined order. The natural numbers are provided as an example of a well-ordered set, illustrating how a starting point is established and maintained within subsets.
07:00 - 07:30: Banach-Tarski Paradox: Multiplying Spheres The chapter discusses the ordering of integers by utilizing Cantor's method, starting at zero and ranking numbers based on their absolute value from zero. This method demonstrates how integers, which extend infinitely in both positive and negative directions, can be systematically ordered. By consistently applying this ordering, integers can be mapped to natural numbers.
07:30 - 08:00: Exploring the Consequences of the Axiom of Choice This chapter delves into the implications of the Axiom of Choice, specifically discussing various methods of well-ordering infinite sets. It highlights different ways of organizing the integers, such as starting from zero and counting towards positive and then negative infinity. Both methods align with the definition of a well-ordering, where a clear starting point exists for the entire set and its subsets.
08:00 - 08:30: Defending the Axiom of Choice Against Criticism The chapter discusses Cantor's work on set theory, including his success in well ordering countably infinite sets. However, the chapter highlights the controversy around his assertion that uncountably infinite sets, such as the real numbers, could also be well ordered. It notes that Cantor had not managed to prove this claim, as all his attempts to do so had failed.
08:30 - 09:00: Godel and Cohen's Contributions to the Understanding of Choice Cantor's unwavering belief in his theorem stemmed from his devout Lutheran faith, which led him to see his mathematical insights as divinely inspired and unassailable. Despite criticism, he remained confident due to his thorough study and his religious conviction that his work reflected a fundamental truth.
09:00 - 09:30: The Mathematical Universe: With or Without Choice The chapter delves into the historical controversy surrounding the well ordering theorem, focusing on the resistance faced by its proponent, Georg Cantor, from the mathematical community. Particularly, it highlights the opposition from Cantor's former teacher, Leopold Kronecker, who was influential in the community and dismissed Cantor's work as fraudulent. This chapter sheds light on the challenges and conflicts faced by mathematicians when proposing revolutionary ideas that lacked immediate proof.
09:30 - 10:00: The Practical Uses and Acceptance of the Axiom of Choice The chapter delves into the life of mathematician Georg Cantor, focusing on his struggles and interactions with fellow mathematician Leopold Kronecker. Cantor faced repeated rejections in his attempts to join the University of Berlin, which he took very personally. This led to a period of intense emotional distress, during which he wrote multiple letters expressing his dissatisfaction and ultimately suffered a nervous breakdown, requiring a stay in a sanitarium.
10:00 - 10:30: The Ongoing Debate: Is the Axiom of Choice "Right?" The chapter discusses the ongoing debate about the validity of the Axiom of Choice in mathematics. It highlights a historical context involving Georg Cantor, who faced personal and professional challenges partially due to his work on well ordering the real numbers. After a period in a sanatorium, Cantor withdrew from mathematics and focused on teaching philosophy. The chapter also describes a significant moment at the 1904 International Congress of Mathematicians, where Julius König announced a proof claiming that Cantor's well ordering theorem was incorrect.
The Man Who Almost Broke Math (And Himself...) Transcription
00:00 - 00:30 - There is a rule in
mathematics that is so simple, you would think it obviously must be true, but if you accept it, you find there are now some line segments that have no length. A sphere without adding anything to it can be turned into
two identical spheres. A hundred plus years of mathematics has been
built on this axiom. It seems intuitive and it works, but it also creates ridiculous paradoxes. So, is it right? Well, it all starts with
the issue of choice.
00:30 - 01:00 Try this, choose a number. I can just pluck a random
number from my head, like 37 or 42, but that is the human brain at work, not a mathematical process. In math, you can't truly
pick things at random because formulas always
give the same result, which is why computers don't have true random number generators. Instead, they usually run an algorithm on your current local
time to generate numbers that appear random.
01:00 - 01:30 So if we can't pick randomly, how do we select anything in math? Well, the only way is to
follow a rule of some sort. So a rule could be always
choose the smallest thing. For example, if we're looking
at whole positive integers, the smallest is one. For prime numbers it would be two, easy, but what about the real numbers? That's any number, positive,
negative, whole, fraction, even irrational like pi
or the square root of two.
01:30 - 02:00 Now try to choose the smallest one. It's impossible. The real numbers stretch
off to negative infinity. Even if we try to fix our rule
by making it super specific, like choose the smallest number after one, we still get stuck. There's 1.01 and then 1.0001, then 1.00000000001 and so on. So really what number comes after one?
02:00 - 02:30 If we can't begin to specify
the order of the real numbers, next and previous, first
and last, we're stuck. The ridiculous part is we
know we have infinite options, but despite that, we can't
figure out how to just pick one. The mission to resolve this
began with one man in 1870. He took on the task of putting the real numbers
in a definitive order, even if it killed him and it nearly did.
02:30 - 03:00 Georg Cantor was a talented
German mathematician who found himself at the
center of a firestorm after publishing one of
his very first papers at the age of 29. For centuries, our understanding of infinity was heavily
influenced by Galileo's 1638 book. It raised a key question, are
there more natural numbers or are there more square numbers? Just looking at them, the square
numbers are more spaced out and they only become more
sparse the higher you go.
03:00 - 03:30 So it would appear there are fewer squares than natural numbers, but Galileo realized he
could draw a line matching every natural number with its own square. And since he could make
this one-to-one mapping, that he knew that the two sets must be exactly the same size. So there are actually just
as many square numbers as there are natural numbers. From this counterintuitive result, Galileo concluded that terms
like more than or less than
03:30 - 04:00 don't apply to infinity, how we normally use them. It's all just one big
concept of foreverness and this view prevailed for centuries. In fact, it's how many people still understand infinity today, but 200 years on, Cantor wasn't satisfied. In 1874, he wondered what if there were two
infinite sets out there that didn't map perfectly to each other? Would they be different infinities?
04:00 - 04:30 So he set out to compare
the natural numbers and the real numbers between zero and one. Cantor started by assuming he
could perfectly map these sets to each other, one-to-one. So he imagined writing
down an infinite list with a natural number on one side and a real number between
zero and one on the other. Since there is no smallest real number, he would just write
them down in any order. Assuming he now has a
complete infinite list, Cantor writes down another real number
04:30 - 05:00 and to do it, he takes the
first digit of the first number and adds one, then the second
digit of the second number, and again, he adds one. He keeps doing this all
the way down the list. If the digit is an eight or a nine, he subtracts
one instead of adding to avoid duplicates, and by the end of this
process, he has written down a real number between zero and one, but that number doesn't
appear anywhere in his list.
05:00 - 05:30 It's different from the first number in the first decimal place, different from the second number in the second decimal place
and so on down the line. It has to be different from
every number on the list by at least one digit,
the digit on the diagonal. That's why this is called
Cantor's Diagonalization Proof and it shows there must be
more real numbers between zero and one than there are
natural numbers extending out to infinity. Cantor had revealed something remarkable. Infinity doesn't come in just one size.
05:30 - 06:00 Some infinities like the set
of square numbers, integers or rational numbers
can be paired perfectly with the natural numbers. You can literally count them,
one, two, three and so on. So Cantor called these
countable infinities, but then there are bigger infinities, Cantor called them uncountable. These infinities like the
set of all real numbers, the complex numbers, they
can't be matched one-to-one with the natural numbers.
06:00 - 06:30 Cantor's results rocked
the mathematical community. After all, how can something that continues forever be
bigger than something else that continues forever? His work was labeled a
horror and a grave disease, but Cantor wasn't discouraged. His success only spurred him
to pursue his even grander goal to show that even uncountably
infinite sets could be placed in a definitive order. What Cantor called a well-order. For a set to be well ordered,
he required two conditions.
06:30 - 07:00 First, the set must have
a clear starting point. And second, every subset,
a collection of items from that set, must also
have a clear starting point. So for example, the natural
numbers are well ordered, there's a starting point, one, and any subset, say six, seven, eight, also has a clear starting point. In this case, six, you always
know which number comes before and which comes next.
07:00 - 07:30 But what about the integers? Integers stretch off to
infinity in both the positive and negative directions. Well Cantor realized
he could just pick zero as the starting point and from there his ordering
went one, negative one, two, negative two, ranking the
integers by their absolute value, their distance from zero. It doesn't matter if you
put the positives first or the negatives first, as
long as you are consistent. Ordering them this way is
actually what allows us to map the integers to the natural numbers
07:30 - 08:00 and see that both sets are the same size, but there are other ways we
could well order the integers. We could start with zero and then have one, two, three, all the way to positive infinity and then negative one,
negative two, negative three, all the way to negative infinity. This is not how we're used to counting, but both of these options
fit the definition of a well ordering. There's a clear starting point, zero, and all their subsets also have
a definitive starting point.
08:00 - 08:30 Cantor had successfully well ordered a set that was infinite in both directions, but it was only countably infinite. In his next book, he published
his well ordering theorem. It claimed that every set, even the uncountably infinite
ones like the real numbers could be well ordered. The problem was he hadn't
actually proven this because he couldn't, every
method he tried had failed,
08:30 - 09:00 but there was one big reason that Cantor was so confident in his theorem. Cantor was a devout Lutheran and he believed God was
speaking through him. He said, my theory
stands as firm as a rock. Every arrow directed
against it will return quickly to its archer. How do I know this? Because I have studied it
from all sides for many years and above all because I have
followed its roots so to speak, to the first infallible
cause of all created things.
09:00 - 09:30 Belief notwithstanding,
the well ordering theorem was a lofty claim to make without any mathematical proof. And so for the second time, the mathematical community attacked and ostracized Cantor. Leading the charge was Leopold Kronecker, the head of mathematics at
the University of Berlin. Kronecker completely dismissed
Cantor's work, labeling him a scientific charlatan and
a corrupter of the youth. And Kronecker used to be Cantor's teacher.
09:30 - 10:00 Cantor dreamed of joining him
at the University of Berlin, but all his applications
were mysteriously denied. So Cantor took the rejection personally. In 1884, he wrote 52 letters to a friend and every one of them bemoaned Kronecker. Soon Cantor suffered
what would be the first of many nervous breakdowns. He was confined to a
sanitarium for recovery. The only way he could prove everyone wrong
10:00 - 10:30 was by well ordering the real numbers, but he couldn't find a
starting point, literally. Once Cantor was released
from the sanatorium, he stepped away from math, a broken man. And over the next 15
years he taught philosophy and rarely dabbled in his old pursuits. Perhaps his greatest challenge came at the 1904 International
Congress of mathematicians. There, Julius König, a respected
professor from Budapest, announced he had proof that Cantor's well
ordering theorem was wrong.
10:30 - 11:00 In the audience was not only Cantor but also his wife, two of his
daughters and his colleagues. He felt utterly humiliated, but there was also another in attendance. Ernst Zermelo. Zermelo was a German mathematician who had recently developed a
keen interest in Cantor's work and as he listened to
König's presentation, something felt off. Within 24 hours, Zermelo
had pinpointed the problem.
11:00 - 11:30 König's proof contained
a damning contradiction, and within a month, Zermello
published a three-page article titled "Proof That Every
Set Can Be Well-Ordered" and it was flawless. Zermelo's breakthrough came
when he discovered something profound in Cantor's work, a mechanism which Cantor
uses unconsciously and instinctively everywhere, but formulates explicitly nowhere. See, all along, Cantor had been assuming
11:30 - 12:00 that he could make an infinite number of choices at once from any set, including uncountable infinite
sets like the real numbers, but this was just an assumption. Nowhere in the mathematical rule book was this explicitly permitted and math is built on
rules, specifically axioms. Axioms are simple statements we accept as true without proof. Zermelo realized Cantor's
assumption needed to be formalized into something that holds up in a system of proof. A new axiom that said, making all
12:00 - 12:30 of those choices was possible. He needed the axiom of choice. - The axiom of choice
can be said in the sense that if you have infinitely many sets and each set is not
empty, then there is a way to choose one element
from each of the sets. - For finite sets, this seems obvious, just go set by set and pick something. Even for infinite sets, it's
easy if there's a clear rule, like always choose the smallest thing, but sometimes there is no natural rule.
12:30 - 13:00 In those cases when you're choosing from infinitely many sets, including the uncountable ones, you need the axiom of choice. We can't say how we're choosing, but the axiom makes all of
these choices all at once. The axiom doesn't allow you to say which element you've chosen, only that infinitely many
choices are possible. So how does this new axiom enable us to well order the real numbers. Zermelo uses the axiom of choice
13:00 - 13:30 to choose a number from the
set of all real numbers. He places this number, let's
call it X1 into a new set, R. The axiom then allows him to choose another number from the subset of all reals minus the one taken out. He calls this number X2 and places it as the
next number in his set and he keeps doing this,
taking the chosen number and placing it next, X3, X4, X5. Now it feels like he's choosing
these numbers one at a time, but in reality the choices are made from all possible
subsets at the same time.
13:30 - 14:00 As Zermelo indexes each number
with the natural numbers, at first it might seem like
he'd run into a problem because the natural numbers
are only accountably infinite, whereas there are way more reals. So he should eventually run out of labels, but we can count beyond infinity. We did it earlier when we
counted past positive infinity to get to negative one,
negative two and so on. So we just need a new set of numbers that extends past the naturals,
call the next number omega,
14:00 - 14:30 then omega plus one,
omega plus two, and so on. These omega numbers are
not bigger than infinity. They just come after infinity. They don't tell us how
many things are there, but they do tell us their order. So the next number we pull
out, we'll label it X omega, then X omega plus one, X
omega plus two, and so on. This will continue until we match the size of the real numbers and
our original set is empty. Now every real number is in our new set.
14:30 - 15:00 There is a first number, X1, and every subset also has a first number. And just like that, we have
successfully well ordered the real numbers. This order looks nothing
like our familiar ordering. A billion could come before 0.2, but with this process, we can prove that a well ordering exists. And more than that, we now
have a way to resolve our issue of how to choose mathematically. We can't pick a smallest real number,
15:00 - 15:30 but now we can pick a first
real number, our starting point, and we can do this for any set, meaning all sets can be well
ordered no matter the infinity. So Cantor's well-ordering theorem and Zermelo's axiom of
choice are equivalent. Cantor was so relieved. Zermelo had proved the
well-ordering theorem and well ordered the real
numbers all in under a month.
15:30 - 16:00 Zermelo took something mathematicians had unknowingly relied on for decades and turned it into a formal axiom. He showed that understanding
math isn't just about numbers, it's about the logic behind them. And lately I've been trying
to do a similar thing, but with AI where I'm trying
to understand the logic behind how models like ChatGPT work, and if you've also wanted to learn how generative AI actually works, well then you can do that with
today's sponsor, Brilliant. Brilliant has just launched a great course that breaks all of this down
with interactive visuals,
16:00 - 16:30 which is exactly what
I love about Brilliant. The course builds your
intuition for the math and logic behind AI, exploring
how models are trained to spot patterns, generate
images, and even whip up a song. ♪ Strandbeest striding
through the sand ♪ Brilliant has thousands of
interactive lessons in math, science, programming, technology and beyond, all designed
to sharpen your thinking and problem solving skills. And since each lesson is bite-sized,
16:30 - 17:00 you can jump in anywhere,
anytime on your laptop or even on your phone. So to try everything Brilliant
has to offer for free for a full 30 days visit
brilliant.org/veritasium, click that link in the description or scan this handy QR code. And if you sign up,
you'll also get 20% off their annual premium subscription. So I want to thank Brilliant
for sponsoring this video. And now back to the axiom of choice. The axiom of choice may
have been a new idea,
17:00 - 17:30 but its use was anything but. Zermelo scanned dozens of
papers from other mathematicians and realized they had also
been using the axiom all along, even those who had
criticized Cantor's work. - It just goes to show
how unintuitive it is that it's even an axiom. People had been using it for
like a decade, unknowingly. - But this almost seems too obvious. Zermelo's proof didn't actually
construct a well order. It just said one must exist,
17:30 - 18:00 but can something exist if
we can't actually build it? His proof also used an
uncountable number of steps, was that even allowed? Some mathematicians argued
proofs should be finite, others accepted infinity,
but only the countable kind and then things got worse. When mathematicians played
around with the axiom of choice, it created disturbing results. One of the first came from
Giuseppe Vitali in 1905. Vitali used the axiom of choice
to build a set of numbers
18:00 - 18:30 that shattered our idea of what it means for something to have length. So what Vitali does is he
takes every real number between zero and one and assigns it to one of
an infinite number of bins. Let's call these bins groups. So we want each real number
to end up in exactly one of our infinite bins. So how does he do it? Well, let's say we have
two numbers, X and Y.
18:30 - 19:00 If their difference, X minus Y is equal to a rational, that is one integer divided by another
integer, well then both X and Y will go into the same bin. But if we have two other
numbers, let's say P and Q and their difference
is not irrational, so it's an irrational difference, well then those two numbers
19:00 - 19:30 will go into separate bins. So let's do some examples. If this is 3/4 minus a half, then we get a quarter and
so both 3/4 and a half will go into the same bin. In fact, you can see that all rational numbers
from this span, zero to one, they'll all end up in the same group. Now if you have irrational numbers, well it's not clear whether
they will go into the same bin
19:30 - 20:00 or not because for example, if we have the number
root two over two minus say root two over two
minus a quarter, well then that does have a rational
difference even though each of these numbers is irrational. So these two numbers will
go into the same group, but if we have irrational
numbers root two over two minus root two over three, well that gives an irrational difference. So root two over three will
have to go into a different bin
20:00 - 20:30 and it will be joined
by all of the numbers it has a rational difference from. And in this way, you can
assign each real number to exactly one of these bins. Next, Vitali used the axiom of choice to reach into each group and select exactly one number, which would be a
representative of the group. So we could pull out 3/4
from the rational group, root two over two from this group, root two over three from
that group and so on.
20:30 - 21:00 Though of course because we're
using the axiom of choice, you don't actually know what
that representative number is, just that you have one. So we could write it down like this. We have these representatives
from each group and together they form the Vitali set. You can visualize this set
as a collection of points between zero and one. Next, Vitali makes
infinite copies of his set and each one he shifts by
a different rational number
21:00 - 21:30 between negative one and positive one. So if you think about what that does, it's gonna move each representative number to be at the position of every
other number in its group. If we just had the one rational
number that we plucked out as a representative
from the rational group, now we're gonna shift it by
every possible rational number between negative one and positive one. So it's going to end up at
every other position occupied by the other members of its
group, at least on the span between zero and one.
21:30 - 22:00 So if you imagine now merging all of these infinite sets together, there's gonna be no
overlap between the points. And second, we are going
to have every real number between zero and one because on that span we have
every member of every group. So now the question is what is the size of the Vitali set? Now we know that the union of those sets must be
greater than or equal to one
22:00 - 22:30 because we have every real
number between zero and one, but also these points only
extend out as far as negative one or positive two. So it must be less than or equal to three, but this is where the problem arises because what number for the size of the Vitali set could you add to itself infinitely many times and end up with a value
between one and three? There is no number like that. I mean if the size of
the Vitali set was zero,
22:30 - 23:00 you add it up infinitely,
many times you still get zero. If the size of the Vitali set
is a small positive value, then you add it up infinitely many times, you're gonna get infinity, not three. So we have a contradiction and the only way out is
if the Vitali set itself is unmeasurable, which seems crazy. Non-measurable sets like the
Vitali set have no consistent definition of size or length
or area or even probability.
23:00 - 23:30 But math is built on the idea that everything can be
quantified, whether it's distance, time, or weight, except now
there are non-measurable sets and it seems like the axiom
of choice is to blame. This was just the start of the
uproar caused by the axiom. In 1924, two mathematicians, Stefan Banach and Alfred Tarski used
it to show something that looks like a magic trick. They proved you could
take a single solid ball and split it into just five pieces,
23:30 - 24:00 and then by carefully rotating and moving those pieces, you could reassemble them
into two balls each identical to the one we started with, and you could keep going until eventually you have
an infinite number of balls, infinity all from one. This sounds absurd, but we can actually see how
it works by building a graph. Imagine you can move in four directions, up, down, left and right.
24:00 - 24:30 After taking a step, say to the left, you get the same four choices,
up, down, left and right, but if you go to the right, you'll end up back where you started. So the only rule we're gonna have is that you can't immediately reverse a move, and we'll keep repeating
this at every step, drawing each new line, half
the size of the previous one so it all fits on the screen. If we keep going, we'll end up with this infinitely branching graph. Looking at our graph, we can
break it into five sections.
24:30 - 25:00 There's the middle
section where we started, and then there are four other sections that are all identical, just rotated. So if we take this section to the left and we move everything
one step to the right, the top part ends up here,
the bottom part here, and the leftmost part here, then we've almost
recreated the entire graph. The only thing we're
missing is this section, so let's add it back in, but we could have done the same thing in a completely different way
by taking the bottom section
25:00 - 25:30 and moving it one step up. Now the leftmost part ends up
here, the rightmost part here and the bottom here. Again, we're just missing one section, so let's add it back in. But this means I can recreate
the entire original graph in two completely different ways. We took one graph, split it into sections, shifted the sections, so the
left section went to the right and the down section up and somehow ended up with
two identical copies.
25:30 - 26:00 This is exactly what
Banach and Tarski did, but with a ball, like our
graph, we again have four moves. We can rotate the ball
up, down, left or right, and again, our only rule is that we can't immediately reverse a move. And to make sure we never
come back to the same point, every rotation will be by the same irrational
portion of a circle. We can pick a random
starting point, mark it and then start rotating the ball. Each point is colored
based on the direction
26:00 - 26:30 of rotation used to get there. If we do this an infinite
number of times, we end up with this collection of points. This is a countably infinite collection because we could list each rotation and assign it a natural number, but the surface of a ball has
uncountably infinite points just like the real number line. So if we want to cover the
entire surface, we would need to repeat this process,
but where do we start next? Since there are uncountably
infinite possible
26:30 - 27:00 starting points, we can't list them all and we wanna be sure to avoid any points we've already colored. So the solution is to
use the axiom of choice. With it, we can choosing
unique starting points, even though we can't say exactly
how we are choosing them. Once we've colored
every point on the ball, we can split the points into five groups, one for the starting points and four others based on
the final rotation used to arrive at those points.
27:00 - 27:30 These groups can now be treated just like the sections of our graph. We can take the group of points that end with a left rotation and
rotate it to the right. Then we add in the group that
ends with a right rotation, and just like that, we've
recreated our original ball and we can do it again making
an extra move to account for the starting points. We can equally take the group
that ends with a down rotation and rotate it upwards. Then we add in the group
that ends with an up rotation and our starting points,
27:30 - 28:00 and now we've recreated our
original ball a second time. Now, this is a bit of
an oversimplification, but it gives you the
essence of how this is done. From one ball, we have
created two identical balls of the same volume, and nothing stops us
from doing this again. Two balls can become
four, four become eight, and before you know it,
you've got infinite balls. - The axiom of choice is
something that's so obviously true and it's consequences
are so obviously false
28:00 - 28:30 that you're like, what
the hell is going on? - This infinite duplication
is theoretically possible, but the catch is the groups
we split the ball into aren't simple shapes. They're actually non-measurable,
just like the Vitali set, although the original ball has a volume and the duplicated balls have a volume, the step in between violates
our understanding of size. This is what allows the paradox to happen. - Of course, those are not
physically plausible cuts, but like there's a more
meta physical question like,
28:30 - 29:00 should this even remotely be possible if we could make such cuts? And the answer to almost
every human I know is absolutely not. - The truth is no one
knew what was going on. That same year, Tarski
tried to push the axiom of choice further proving it
is equivalent to the statement that squaring any infinite set
would not increase its size. When Tarski first submitted
this work to a journal in Paris, the editor Lebesgue
responded dismissively,
29:00 - 29:30 nobody's interested in the equivalence between two false statements. Not to be deterred, Tarski
sent it to a different editor at the same journal, Freche, his response, nobody's interested in the equivalence of two obviously true statements. Tarski never submitted
a paper there again. So math was in crisis for over 30 years with people not knowing what to believe. - The question is, wait a
second, is this really an axiom
29:30 - 30:00 or is this something that you can prove? - In 1938, we finally
started getting some answers. The Austrian mathematician, Kurt Godel, proved there is a world all
the other already accepted axioms of set theory hold true, and so does the axiom of choice. Then in 1963, Paul Cohen
proved there's also a world where all the axioms
of set theory hold true except for the axiom of choice. This is kind of like the
parallel postulate in geometry.
30:00 - 30:30 You can think of geometry as a game. The first four postulates or axioms are like the
minimum rules required to play that game, and then the fifth axiom selects the universe
that you wanna play in. If you choose that the
fifth axiom doesn't hold, so there are no parallel lines, then you're playing in spherical geometry. If you choose one parallel line, you're playing in flat geometry, and if you choose more
than one parallel line, then you're playing in
hyperbolic geometry. All of these geometries are valid.
30:30 - 31:00 It just depends on the
math you want to do, and it's the same for the axiom of choice. The axiom of choice can neither be proven nor disproven from the other axioms. So as long as the other
axioms are consistent, adding choice won't lead
to any contradictions. Paul Cohen was awarded the
Fields Medal three years later for his groundbreaking result, as well as his other work in
set theory, and after Godel and Cohen's work, most of the debates
31:00 - 31:30 about the axiom of choice died down. - In the end, what the hell
is going on is that it's up to you whether you want to
choose for the axiom of choice to be a part of your system or not, and face the consequences of either having it or not having it. - Despite the counterintuitive
results created by the axiom of choice,
like non-measurable sets and infinite duplication, it is incredibly useful,
choice allows mathematicians to replace lengthy explicit proofs with more concise arguments.
31:30 - 32:00 By proving statements in the finite case, many proofs can be extended to any infinite case in just one line. This reduces proofs that
could have been 20 pages to just half a page. And the axiom of choice
doesn't just make math easier. It is essential to some proofs. There are many theorems
where the general case can't be proven without
using choice somewhere. Now, some mathematicians still
prefer proofs without choice, even if it's harder, the proof has to be spelled
out step by step to generalize
32:00 - 32:30 to infinite cases, and this
provides additional information. Some mathematicians spend
their time studying universes without the axiom of choice to understand what happens when we remove it. But today, the axiom of choice is almost universally accepted. For the past 80 plus years,
generations of mathematicians have been taught with choice as a given to the point where many
who use the axiom of choice might not even realize
when they're doing it. - If you don't include
the axiom of choice,
32:30 - 33:00 then you're kind of working with both hands tied behind your back. It's very hard to make any
progress on modern math. - So the question was never really is the axiom of choice right? But rather is the axiom of choice right for what you want to do? (frequencies buzzing) (bright music)