Why Be Moral When You Can Get Away With Evil? Glaucon’s Challenge in Plato’s Republic
Estimated read time: 1:20
Learn to use AI like a Pro
Get the latest AI workflows to boost your productivity and business performance, delivered weekly by expert consultants. Enjoy step-by-step guides, weekly Q&A sessions, and full access to our AI workflow archive.
Summary
In this thought-provoking video on Glaucon's challenge in Plato's Republic, the age-old question of morality and its intrinsic versus instrumental value is dissected. Taking cues from the ever-relevant Glaucon and his arguments about the nature of justice, the video delves into philosophical debates on whether morality is pursued for its own sake or for external recognition and benefits. It intricately weaves in the timeless example of the Ring of Gyges alongside Socrates's rebuttal on justice as harmonious soul balance, inviting viewers to introspect on the true essence of being moral.
Highlights
Have you ever acted immorally just because you could? 🙈
Is our morality purely out of convenience and fear of being caught? 🕵️♀️
Glaucon argues justice is just social pressure to behave! 💼
Socrates sees justice as a path to a harmonious soul. ✨
Does power corrupt absolutely? Ask Gyges! 💪
Would you remain just if you could be invisible? 🧙♂️
Key Takeaways
Why do good when you can get away with evil? 🤔
Is morality just a social contract? 🤝
Socrates versus Glaucon: A battle of morals! ⚔️
The power of the Ring of Gyges: Temptation unleashed! 💍
Justice: Burden or virtue? You decide! ⚖️
Overview
Imagine having a magical ring that gives you the power to do anything without anyone knowing. Would you still choose to do good? This video takes us deep into the philosophical underpinnings of morality, as discussed by Glaucon and Socrates. With stark contrasts between perceived justice and intrinsic virtue, it questions our deepest motivations behind moral actions.
Plato's narrative through Glaucon provocatively presents the notion that morality is merely a social tool to avert chaos—a restraint we impose to live in peace. The Ring of Gyges serves as a powerful metaphor for unchecked power, challenging us to confront our real reasons for morality. The conversation heats up with Socrates's intervention, advocating for justice as a crucial element of soul harmony.
As we explore Socrates's arguments on justice being inherent to our well-being, the question remains: is it better to seem just or be just? This piece invites introspection on whether justice is an integral part of a fulfilled life or simply a mask we wear for social benefits. The philosophical debate lives on, asking each of us—what would you do if no one was watching?
Chapters
00:00 - 00:30: Introduction and Moral Question The chapter delves into the concept of moral behavior driven by consequence rather than intrinsic values. It questions whether actions deemed unacceptable would still occur if there were no punitive repercussions. Through examples like lying, privacy invasion, and feigned illness to avoid responsibilities, it challenges the reader to consider if their ethical actions are motivated by genuine integrity or merely the fear of being punished. This philosophical inquiry encourages introspection into one's true motivations behind moral behavior.
00:30 - 01:30: Instrumental Morality and Societal Views The chapter "Instrumental Morality and Societal Views" explores the concept of morality as instrumental, suggesting that individuals are moral because it is convenient rather than due to any inherent value of morality. The chapter highlights the tension between this view and the belief held by many that morality is absolute, indubitable, or divinely ordained, independent of societal norms. It emphasizes that even if everyone in society behaves immorally, it does not justify individual immoral actions.
03:00 - 04:30: The Three Kinds of Good The chapter "The Three Kinds of Good" delves into the concept of morality as an intrinsic responsibility that surpasses societal approval or individual gain. Socrates exemplifies this through his unwavering adherence to his values, even in the face of execution. Similarly, the teachings of Jesus Christ suggest that true goodness transcends social advantages, implying a deeper, more profound aspect of being good. The chapter highlights this idea by discussing historical figures who embody these principles through their actions and beliefs.
04:30 - 05:30: Justice as a Burden This chapter delves into the concept of justice as both a moral and social construct. It explores the perspective that some are persecuted for righteousness and that justice can be viewed as a divine right, as reflected in the phrase 'theirs is the kingdom of heaven'. Contrary to this, there is an opposing view that considers justice and morality as mere social constructs, existing simply as a mutually agreed upon set of rules to prevent chaos and self-interest from prevailing. This agreement arises not out of intrinsic value for justice, but as a necessary measure to avoid a state of anarchy and fear. Overall, the chapter presents justice as a necessary burden—a compromise between individual self-interest and collective security.
06:00 - 09:30: The Ring of Gyges and Its Implications The concept of morality is discussed as a form of calculated restraint, where individuals give up certain freedoms in exchange for a societal agreement where others do the same. This mutual restraint is viewed as a means to achieve peace rather than being seen as a higher moral calling. The chapter references Glaucon’s argument in Plato’s "The Republic," suggesting that people act justly not out of inherent virtue but out of fear of consequences and the desire for a good reputation.
11:00 - 15:30: Socrates’s Response: Justice as Soul Harmony In the video, a fragment from Plato's Republic is discussed, focusing on Glaucon's argument for viewing justice as an instrumental value rather than valuable in itself. Glaucon uses the example of a ring of invisibility, which inspired Tolkien, to illustrate his point. The video also briefly explores Plato's response to Glaucon's evidence, aiming to deepen the viewer's understanding of morality.
16:00 - 17:30: Conclusion: The Choice of Justice and Morality This chapter delves into the concepts of justice and morality, challenging readers to consider their own definitions and understandings of these principles. It references a classification of goods from Plato's 'Republic,' as described by Glaucon, dividing goods into three categories. The first category includes things valuable in themselves, such as joy, love, happiness, and aesthetic appreciation, which are desired for their inherent value rather than for any results they might lead to.
Why Be Moral When You Can Get Away With Evil? Glaucon’s Challenge in Plato’s Republic Transcription
00:00 - 00:30 Have you ever done something bad simply because
you knew there wouldn’t be any consequences? You might have lied about things because there
was no way people would have figured out the truth. Or maybe you read private messages on
someone else’s phone when the person wasn’t around. Perhaps you called in sick to work or
skipped school even when you were perfectly healthy. In any case, you did something that
was not socially acceptable, assuming that you would not be punished for your actions.
So you might have thought: “Why not do it?” This basic experience everyone is familiar
with ties into a serious philosophical problem: if your motivation for acting righteously arises
out of fear of punishment, it seems to follow that
00:30 - 01:00 morality is purely instrumental; namely, that we
are moral because it is convenient for us and not due to the internal value of being moral.
However, there is tension here—many people believe that morality is indubitable, absolute,
or even divine, and that it is not contingent on social order. If everyone in society acts in an
immoral way, it does not mean that you should as
01:00 - 01:30 well. There seems to be a sense of internal
responsibility in what it means to be moral, something larger than merely fear of
social disapproval or self-interest. That’s what Socrates demonstrates
through his personal example before being executed. He refuses to abandon
his values and his understanding of what is right and what is wrong. Jesus
Christ seems to convey a similar message: there is something greater in the idea of being
good than merely social benefits. “Blessed are
01:30 - 02:00 those who are persecuted for righteousness'
sake, for theirs is the kingdom of heaven.” At the same time, there are opponents of this
view. They claim that justice and morality is nothing more than a social contract. Left entirely
free, people would pursue their own self-interest, even at the expense of others. But since no
one wants to live in constant fear of being harmed or exploited, they collectively
agree to abide by rules—not because they value justice intrinsically, but because
it is the lesser evil compared to anarchy.
02:00 - 02:30 In this framework, morality is
a kind of calculated restraint: we give up some freedom (like the freedom to steal
or deceive) in return for a society where others also restrain themselves. Justice, then, is not
a higher calling or inner virtue—it is simply the price we pay for peace. This line of thought
echoes Glaucon’s argument in The Republic, where he claims that people act justly
only because they fear the consequences of being unjust and because they seek the
rewards that come with a good reputation.
02:30 - 03:00 In this video, we’ll discuss a fragment from
Plato’s Republic in which Glaucon delivers the strongest argument for why we should see
justice as something instrumental rather than as valuable in itself. We’ll cover
his example of the ring of invisibility, the very one that inspired Tolkien in his
fiction. We'll also take a quick look at Plato’s response to the evidence Glaucon
presents. By the end of the video, you will have a deeper understanding of what it means
to be moral; you might reinforce your current
03:00 - 03:30 understanding of morality, or you may change it
entirely, being convinced by one of the sides. The Three Kinds of Good In the second chapter of the Republic
Glaucon divides goods into three types: The first is things valuable because of
themselves. His examples are joy and 'all the harmless pleasures that have no results beyond the
joy of having them.' You can also think of love, happiness, contemplation, and aesthetic
appreciation—all the things we desire not because of what they lead to, but for
their own sake. We don’t seek pleasure
03:30 - 04:00 as a means to something else; we seek it
because we consider it valuable in itself. The second type of goods includes things that
are valuable because of their consequences—for example, physical training, medicine, and
money. We desire these things because they bring us something we consider inherently
valuable. We don’t want chocolate for its own sake; we want it because it brings us pleasure.
So, chocolate is valuable as a means of obtaining something we value in itself. It plays the role
of an instrument for getting what we truly want.
04:00 - 04:30 The third and highest type of goods includes
things that are valuable both in themselves and because of their consequences.
Glaucon’s examples are knowing, seeing, and being healthy. Another good example
is friendship. Having friends definitely brings many benefits, such as support,
emotional stability, and a sense of joy and happiness. But we seem to value friendship
as something special—something not reducible
04:30 - 05:00 to any of these things. So, friendship
is both useful and inherently valuable. Justice as a Burden So where does justice fit in? Well,
as we pointed out in the introduction, there is a disagreement here. Plato believes
that justice belongs to the highest type of goods – it is valuable both for its own sake and
for the results it brings. Glaucon also tends to think so. But he wants to figure out the truth.
So he attempts to defend an alternative view, which he refers to as the general opinion. It’s
proponents say ‘Justice belongs to the onerous
05:00 - 05:30 kind, and is to be practiced for the sake of
the rewards and popularity that come from a reputation for justice, but is to be avoided
because of itself as something burdensome.’ Here we can clearly see that this opinion places
justice in the second type of goods, the ones valuable only for their consequences. We also see
that justice is described as «onerous», meaning it brings a certain discomfort. The fact that the
rewards come from a reputation for justice is
05:30 - 06:00 also important to keep in mind, because Glaucon
will expand on this idea later in his speech. Let’s first figure out why justice is onerous.
It is mainly because It goes against our natural desires – people often want to act unjustly
when it benefits them—lying, cheating, taking more than their share. Justice,
by contrast, requires self-restraint, sacrifice, and denying oneself
certain pleasures or advantages. So, it's experienced as a constraint
on what we naturally want to do.
06:00 - 06:30 The Ring of Gyges But where does justice come from? Why do we even need to consider being just if
it goes against our instincts? Glaucon explains that those who defend this
view say that doing injustice is naturally good, while suffering it is bad. But because the
harm of suffering injustice outweighs the benefit of committing it, people agree to
avoid both. They make laws and call what the law commands “just.” Justice, then, is a
compromise — a middle point between the best
06:30 - 07:00 (doing injustice freely) and the worst (being
wronged with no revenge). «People value it not as a good but because they are too weak
to do injustice with impunity.» A truly powerful person wouldn’t bother with such
an agreement. He would do whatever he wants because people naturally have «the desire
to outdo others and get more and more.» That’s quite a cruel view on justice and is
popular nowadays as well as in the times of Plato. To illustrate this point, Glaucon tells
a story of the magical ring found by Gyges.
07:00 - 07:30 Gyges was a shepherd serving the king of
Lydia. One day, after a violent earthquake, the ground split open near where he was
watching his flock. Curious, he went down into the opening and discovered a strange scene: a
giant bronze horse, hollow and with doors. Inside, he found a massive corpse, wearing only
a gold ring. He took the ring and left.
07:30 - 08:00 Later, during a meeting with other
shepherds, Gyges discovered that turning the ring's collet inward made him
invisible. Realizing the power he now held, he managed to get sent to the royal
court. There, he seduced the queen, and with her help conspired against the
king and slew him, and took the kingdom. The ring here serves as a metaphor for
power gained unjustly. Similarly to how Gyges used his invisibility to gain control
over the kingdom, ordinary people often
08:00 - 08:30 gain benefits by lies and manipulations,
remaining in a sense invisible to others. The Just vs. the Unjust Life Glaucon then suggests a following thought
experiment: let’s say there were two magical rings—one worn by a just person, the other by an
unjust one—and both gave their wearer the power to act without consequences. It’s hard to believe
that anyone, no matter how virtuous, would resist the temptation to abandon justice or avoid taking
what isn’t theirs. No one would stay honest or
08:30 - 09:00 respect others' property if they could do whatever
they wanted without punishment. Some might say this clearly shows that people are never just by
choice, but only because they’re forced to be. That is already a very strong point but Glaucon
doesn’t stop here. He then pushes it even further and suggests to imagine two different people:
one fully just and one fully unjust. Imagine that the first person manages to slip away with his
injustice and never get caught and, in fact, is believed to be just in the society and is praised
for his good deeds. While the second person does
09:00 - 09:30 only good actions and is accused of being unjust
and is punished and persecuted in the society much like Plato’s teacher Socrates or Jesus Christ.
Glaucon’s question is who will be happy and who will be unhappy? This is probably the most fierce illustration to show that justice is
not valuable in itself. After all, how can we stand our ground if no one
believes in us and accuses us of wrongdoing?
09:30 - 10:00 «They’ll say that a just person in
such circumstances will be whipped, stretched on a rack, chained,
blinded with fire, and, at the end, when he has suffered every kind of evil, he’ll be
impaled, and will realize then that one shouldn’t want to be just but to be
believed to be just.» That’s where it gets clear that what we
truly want is not to be just but to have a reputation for justice. Because this
reputation gives us all the benefits. A
10:00 - 10:30 truly unjust person knows how the world
really works and doesn’t care about what others think. He doesn’t want the image of
being unjust he wants to be unjust for real while being perceived as the opposite. He’s smart
and strategic. Because people believe he’s just, he gains power, marries into any family he
wants, arranges good marriages for his kids, makes deals with anyone, and gets all the
benefits—without feeling bad about doing wrong. At this point, it seems impossible to
rehabilitate the concept of justice in
10:30 - 11:00 the face of cynicism. Glaucon has convincingly
shown that justice is valued not for its own sake, but as a useful instrument—and more importantly,
that it is the appearance of justice, rather than justice itself, that holds real value. As long
as we avoid being caught in our injustices, as long as no one sees the harm we commit,
we are regarded as successful. Justice seems entirely discredited. Why be good when no one is
watching, and being bad brings rewards? Glaucon
11:00 - 11:30 has forced us into a corner. And it is from
this corner that Socrates begins to push back. Socrates’s Response: Justice as Soul Harmony Socrates’s response to this
challenge is quite complex, so it won’t be covered in detail in this video.
Instead, I’d like to focus on his strategy, as it offers a general understanding of what he
aims to do in defending the concept of justice. He begins his defense by proposing that we
should first search for what justice is and how it manifests. This seems reasonable, since
if we are to argue about something, we must first
11:30 - 12:00 understand what it is, rather than merely discuss
how it benefits or harms us. To achieve this, he examines how justice appears in society. His idea
is that because justice exists both in the state and in the individual, it is better to investigate
justice in the state first. The reason is that the state is larger, and therefore, as he puts
it, "there is more justice in the larger thing, and it will be easier to learn what it is."
Some philosophers have criticized this method,
12:00 - 12:30 arguing that Socrates blurs the line between two
different kinds of justice—political justice in the state and psychological justice in the
soul. They claim it's incoherent to assume that what makes a society just is the same
as what makes an individual just. However, others argue that his reasoning is not based
on mere analogy, but rather on a structural similarity and deep interconnectedness between
the state and the individual. For Socrates, the city and the soul reflect each other not
superficially, but in the way their internal
12:30 - 13:00 parts are organized and how they function
together to produce harmony and justice. This interconnectedness is precisely why
Socrates devotes so much attention to education and cultural formation in The Republic.
He believes that the development of justice in the soul is inseparable from the social and cultural
environment in which a person is raised. Children, especially at a young age, mimic everything they
are exposed to and absorb models of behavior from
13:00 - 13:30 their surroundings. Once these patterns take root
in early life, they become nearly impossible to change later. Therefore, if we want individuals
to have a just organization of the psyche, they must be exposed to just influences from
the beginning—and such influences can only be reliably provided by a just state.
For this reason, the state’s primary role is to create conditions that foster
the growth of justice within individuals.
13:30 - 14:00 All citizens must learn music to internalize
harmony and develop a sense of temperance, especially in relation to food and sensual
pleasures. This helps keep their appetites in check. Those naturally inclined toward courage
and physical strength—future warriors—must be surrounded by stories of bravery and nobility
so that these qualities are solidified in their characters. Philosophers, on the other hand,
must be immersed in wisdom and knowledge to learn how to govern justly and pursue truth.
Through this comprehensive cultural shaping,
14:00 - 14:30 the state transmits justice into
the souls of its inhabitants. Yet the relationship works both ways: just
individuals also help sustain and reinforce the justice of the state. When someone is raised in a
just environment and develops a harmonious psyche, they are naturally inclined to act justly. These
just actions, in turn, influence others—especially children—who observe and internalize these
patterns. For instance, a just warrior who consistently demonstrates bravery and moderation
provides a living example for his children,
14:30 - 15:00 who absorb this model of behavior and become
brave themselves, further reinforcing the state’s justice. In this way, justice flows in
both directions—from the state into the soul, and from the soul back into the state.
Thus, Socrates shows us that justice is not merely a social structure or an abstract
ideal, but a lived process of internalization and externalization. It is shaped by our surroundings
and, once rooted in the soul, becomes a force that
15:00 - 15:30 shapes society in return. His investigation is
grounded in careful observations of how cultural influences affect psychological development and
how the state and individual, like mirror images, co-create one another in the pursuit of justice.
But this vision also serves a deeper purpose: it provides a philosophical foundation for
why justice is not merely instrumental. If the just soul is one in which reason rules
over spirit and appetite, and where each part
15:30 - 16:00 performs its proper function in harmony, then
being just means being psychologically healthy, internally ordered, and at peace. An unjust
person, by contrast, suffers from inner conflict, with lower desires overpowering reason and leading
to a kind of self-inflicted tyranny. Socrates ultimately argues that justice is valuable in
itself because it constitutes the well-being of the soul. Just as physical health is
desirable not because of external praise but
16:00 - 16:30 because it makes us function better and feel
whole, so too is justice something we should pursue regardless of rewards or recognition.
In this way, Socrates answers Glaucon not by appealing to fear or reputation, but by showing
that the truly just life is the most fulfilling one, even if it comes with suffering and
misunderstanding. Justice is not a mask we wear to gain favor—it's a condition of
the soul we cultivate for its own sake, because to live justly is to live well.
What Would You Choose? So, what does it truly mean to be moral?
Is it simply about avoiding punishment and
16:30 - 17:00 gaining approval, or is there something
deeper—a kind of harmony within the soul that makes justice desirable in itself? «For
what will it profit a man if he gains the whole world and forfeits his soul? Or what
shall a man give in return for his soul?» Glaucon challenges us to confront our darkest
temptations and to ask whether we would still act morally if no one could see us. But
Socrates invites us to look inward—to see justice not as a burden, but as the very
structure of a healthy, fulfilled life.
17:00 - 17:30 This is not an easy position to hold in a world
that often rewards appearances over substance. But perhaps that’s what makes it so powerful.
When we choose to act justly even when no one is watching—when we cultivate inner order rather
than chase external praise—we are choosing to live a life of meaning, not convenience.
So, I leave you with this question: If you had the ring of Gyges—if no one could see
what you did—would you still choose to be just?
17:30 - 18:00 Let me know in the comments below what
your answer is—and why. Would you side with Glaucon’s realism or Socrates’s idealism?
And if this made you think more deeply about your own moral compass, consider subscribing
for more philosophical content like this.