Exploring Glaucon's Challenge in Plato's Republic

Why Be Moral When You Can Get Away With Evil? Glaucon’s Challenge in Plato’s Republic

Estimated read time: 1:20

    Learn to use AI like a Pro

    Get the latest AI workflows to boost your productivity and business performance, delivered weekly by expert consultants. Enjoy step-by-step guides, weekly Q&A sessions, and full access to our AI workflow archive.

    Canva Logo
    Claude AI Logo
    Google Gemini Logo
    HeyGen Logo
    Hugging Face Logo
    Microsoft Logo
    OpenAI Logo
    Zapier Logo
    Canva Logo
    Claude AI Logo
    Google Gemini Logo
    HeyGen Logo
    Hugging Face Logo
    Microsoft Logo
    OpenAI Logo
    Zapier Logo

    Summary

    In this thought-provoking video on Glaucon's challenge in Plato's Republic, the age-old question of morality and its intrinsic versus instrumental value is dissected. Taking cues from the ever-relevant Glaucon and his arguments about the nature of justice, the video delves into philosophical debates on whether morality is pursued for its own sake or for external recognition and benefits. It intricately weaves in the timeless example of the Ring of Gyges alongside Socrates's rebuttal on justice as harmonious soul balance, inviting viewers to introspect on the true essence of being moral.

      Highlights

      • Have you ever acted immorally just because you could? 🙈
      • Is our morality purely out of convenience and fear of being caught? 🕵️‍♀️
      • Glaucon argues justice is just social pressure to behave! 💼
      • Socrates sees justice as a path to a harmonious soul. ✨
      • Does power corrupt absolutely? Ask Gyges! 💪
      • Would you remain just if you could be invisible? 🧙‍♂️

      Key Takeaways

      • Why do good when you can get away with evil? 🤔
      • Is morality just a social contract? 🤝
      • Socrates versus Glaucon: A battle of morals! ⚔️
      • The power of the Ring of Gyges: Temptation unleashed! 💍
      • Justice: Burden or virtue? You decide! ⚖️

      Overview

      Imagine having a magical ring that gives you the power to do anything without anyone knowing. Would you still choose to do good? This video takes us deep into the philosophical underpinnings of morality, as discussed by Glaucon and Socrates. With stark contrasts between perceived justice and intrinsic virtue, it questions our deepest motivations behind moral actions.

        Plato's narrative through Glaucon provocatively presents the notion that morality is merely a social tool to avert chaos—a restraint we impose to live in peace. The Ring of Gyges serves as a powerful metaphor for unchecked power, challenging us to confront our real reasons for morality. The conversation heats up with Socrates's intervention, advocating for justice as a crucial element of soul harmony.

          As we explore Socrates's arguments on justice being inherent to our well-being, the question remains: is it better to seem just or be just? This piece invites introspection on whether justice is an integral part of a fulfilled life or simply a mask we wear for social benefits. The philosophical debate lives on, asking each of us—what would you do if no one was watching?

            Chapters

            • 00:00 - 00:30: Introduction and Moral Question The chapter delves into the concept of moral behavior driven by consequence rather than intrinsic values. It questions whether actions deemed unacceptable would still occur if there were no punitive repercussions. Through examples like lying, privacy invasion, and feigned illness to avoid responsibilities, it challenges the reader to consider if their ethical actions are motivated by genuine integrity or merely the fear of being punished. This philosophical inquiry encourages introspection into one's true motivations behind moral behavior.
            • 00:30 - 01:30: Instrumental Morality and Societal Views The chapter "Instrumental Morality and Societal Views" explores the concept of morality as instrumental, suggesting that individuals are moral because it is convenient rather than due to any inherent value of morality. The chapter highlights the tension between this view and the belief held by many that morality is absolute, indubitable, or divinely ordained, independent of societal norms. It emphasizes that even if everyone in society behaves immorally, it does not justify individual immoral actions.
            • 03:00 - 04:30: The Three Kinds of Good The chapter "The Three Kinds of Good" delves into the concept of morality as an intrinsic responsibility that surpasses societal approval or individual gain. Socrates exemplifies this through his unwavering adherence to his values, even in the face of execution. Similarly, the teachings of Jesus Christ suggest that true goodness transcends social advantages, implying a deeper, more profound aspect of being good. The chapter highlights this idea by discussing historical figures who embody these principles through their actions and beliefs.
            • 04:30 - 05:30: Justice as a Burden This chapter delves into the concept of justice as both a moral and social construct. It explores the perspective that some are persecuted for righteousness and that justice can be viewed as a divine right, as reflected in the phrase 'theirs is the kingdom of heaven'. Contrary to this, there is an opposing view that considers justice and morality as mere social constructs, existing simply as a mutually agreed upon set of rules to prevent chaos and self-interest from prevailing. This agreement arises not out of intrinsic value for justice, but as a necessary measure to avoid a state of anarchy and fear. Overall, the chapter presents justice as a necessary burden—a compromise between individual self-interest and collective security.
            • 06:00 - 09:30: The Ring of Gyges and Its Implications The concept of morality is discussed as a form of calculated restraint, where individuals give up certain freedoms in exchange for a societal agreement where others do the same. This mutual restraint is viewed as a means to achieve peace rather than being seen as a higher moral calling. The chapter references Glaucon’s argument in Plato’s "The Republic," suggesting that people act justly not out of inherent virtue but out of fear of consequences and the desire for a good reputation.
            • 11:00 - 15:30: Socrates’s Response: Justice as Soul Harmony In the video, a fragment from Plato's Republic is discussed, focusing on Glaucon's argument for viewing justice as an instrumental value rather than valuable in itself. Glaucon uses the example of a ring of invisibility, which inspired Tolkien, to illustrate his point. The video also briefly explores Plato's response to Glaucon's evidence, aiming to deepen the viewer's understanding of morality.
            • 16:00 - 17:30: Conclusion: The Choice of Justice and Morality This chapter delves into the concepts of justice and morality, challenging readers to consider their own definitions and understandings of these principles. It references a classification of goods from Plato's 'Republic,' as described by Glaucon, dividing goods into three categories. The first category includes things valuable in themselves, such as joy, love, happiness, and aesthetic appreciation, which are desired for their inherent value rather than for any results they might lead to.

            Why Be Moral When You Can Get Away With Evil? Glaucon’s Challenge in Plato’s Republic Transcription

            • 00:00 - 00:30 Have you ever done something bad simply because  you knew there wouldn’t be any consequences? You   might have lied about things because there  was no way people would have figured out the   truth. Or maybe you read private messages on  someone else’s phone when the person wasn’t   around. Perhaps you called in sick to work or  skipped school even when you were perfectly   healthy. In any case, you did something that  was not socially acceptable, assuming that   you would not be punished for your actions.  So you might have thought: “Why not do it?” This basic experience everyone is familiar  with ties into a serious philosophical problem:   if your motivation for acting righteously arises  out of fear of punishment, it seems to follow that
            • 00:30 - 01:00 morality is purely instrumental; namely, that we  are moral because it is convenient for us and not   due to the internal value of being moral. However, there is tension here—many people   believe that morality is indubitable, absolute,  or even divine, and that it is not contingent on   social order. If everyone in society acts in an  immoral way, it does not mean that you should as
            • 01:00 - 01:30 well. There seems to be a sense of internal  responsibility in what it means to be moral,   something larger than merely fear of  social disapproval or self-interest. That’s what Socrates demonstrates  through his personal example before   being executed. He refuses to abandon  his values and his understanding of   what is right and what is wrong. Jesus  Christ seems to convey a similar message:   there is something greater in the idea of being  good than merely social benefits. “Blessed are
            • 01:30 - 02:00 those who are persecuted for righteousness'  sake, for theirs is the kingdom of heaven.” At the same time, there are opponents of this  view. They claim that justice and morality is   nothing more than a social contract. Left entirely  free, people would pursue their own self-interest,   even at the expense of others. But since no  one wants to live in constant fear of being   harmed or exploited, they collectively  agree to abide by rules—not because they   value justice intrinsically, but because  it is the lesser evil compared to anarchy.
            • 02:00 - 02:30 In this framework, morality is  a kind of calculated restraint:   we give up some freedom (like the freedom to steal  or deceive) in return for a society where others   also restrain themselves. Justice, then, is not  a higher calling or inner virtue—it is simply the   price we pay for peace. This line of thought  echoes Glaucon’s argument in The Republic,   where he claims that people act justly  only because they fear the consequences   of being unjust and because they seek the  rewards that come with a good reputation.
            • 02:30 - 03:00 In this video, we’ll discuss a fragment from  Plato’s Republic in which Glaucon delivers the   strongest argument for why we should see  justice as something instrumental rather   than as valuable in itself. We’ll cover  his example of the ring of invisibility,   the very one that inspired Tolkien in his  fiction. We'll also take a quick look at   Plato’s response to the evidence Glaucon  presents. By the end of the video, you will   have a deeper understanding of what it means  to be moral; you might reinforce your current
            • 03:00 - 03:30 understanding of morality, or you may change it  entirely, being convinced by one of the sides. The Three Kinds of Good In the second chapter of the Republic  Glaucon divides goods into three types: The first is things valuable because of  themselves. His examples are joy and 'all the   harmless pleasures that have no results beyond the  joy of having them.' You can also think of love,   happiness, contemplation, and aesthetic  appreciation—all the things we desire not   because of what they lead to, but for  their own sake. We don’t seek pleasure
            • 03:30 - 04:00 as a means to something else; we seek it  because we consider it valuable in itself. The second type of goods includes things that  are valuable because of their consequences—for   example, physical training, medicine, and  money. We desire these things because they   bring us something we consider inherently  valuable. We don’t want chocolate for its own   sake; we want it because it brings us pleasure.  So, chocolate is valuable as a means of obtaining   something we value in itself. It plays the role  of an instrument for getting what we truly want.
            • 04:00 - 04:30 The third and highest type of goods includes  things that are valuable both in themselves   and because of their consequences.  Glaucon’s examples are knowing, seeing,   and being healthy. Another good example  is friendship. Having friends definitely   brings many benefits, such as support,  emotional stability, and a sense of joy   and happiness. But we seem to value friendship  as something special—something not reducible
            • 04:30 - 05:00 to any of these things. So, friendship  is both useful and inherently valuable. Justice as a Burden So where does justice fit in? Well,  as we pointed out in the introduction,   there is a disagreement here. Plato believes  that justice belongs to the highest type of   goods – it is valuable both for its own sake and  for the results it brings. Glaucon also tends to   think so. But he wants to figure out the truth.  So he attempts to defend an alternative view,   which he refers to as the general opinion. It’s  proponents say ‘Justice belongs to the onerous
            • 05:00 - 05:30 kind, and is to be practiced for the sake of  the rewards and popularity that come from a   reputation for justice, but is to be avoided  because of itself as something burdensome.’  Here we can clearly see that this opinion places  justice in the second type of goods, the ones   valuable only for their consequences. We also see  that justice is described as «onerous», meaning it   brings a certain discomfort. The fact that the  rewards come from a reputation for justice is
            • 05:30 - 06:00 also important to keep in mind, because Glaucon  will expand on this idea later in his speech. Let’s first figure out why justice is onerous.  It is mainly because It goes against our natural   desires – people often want to act unjustly  when it benefits them—lying, cheating,   taking more than their share. Justice,  by contrast, requires self-restraint,   sacrifice, and denying oneself  certain pleasures or advantages.   So, it's experienced as a constraint  on what we naturally want to do.
            • 06:00 - 06:30 The Ring of Gyges But where does justice come from? Why do we even   need to consider being just if  it goes against our instincts? Glaucon explains that those who defend this  view say that doing injustice is naturally good,   while suffering it is bad. But because the  harm of suffering injustice outweighs the   benefit of committing it, people agree to  avoid both. They make laws and call what   the law commands “just.” Justice, then, is a  compromise — a middle point between the best
            • 06:30 - 07:00 (doing injustice freely) and the worst (being  wronged with no revenge). «People value it not   as a good but because they are too weak  to do injustice with impunity.» A truly   powerful person wouldn’t bother with such  an agreement. He would do whatever he wants   because people naturally have «the desire  to outdo others and get more and more.» That’s quite a cruel view on justice and is  popular nowadays as well as in the times of   Plato. To illustrate this point, Glaucon tells  a story of the magical ring found by Gyges.
            • 07:00 - 07:30 Gyges was a shepherd serving the king of  Lydia. One day, after a violent earthquake,   the ground split open near where he was  watching his flock. Curious, he went down   into the opening and discovered a strange scene: a  giant bronze horse, hollow and with doors. Inside,   he found a massive corpse, wearing only  a gold ring. He took the ring and left.
            • 07:30 - 08:00 Later, during a meeting with other  shepherds, Gyges discovered that   turning the ring's collet inward made him  invisible. Realizing the power he now held,   he managed to get sent to the royal  court. There, he seduced the queen,   and with her help conspired against the  king and slew him, and took the kingdom. The ring here serves as a metaphor for  power gained unjustly. Similarly to how   Gyges used his invisibility to gain control  over the kingdom, ordinary people often
            • 08:00 - 08:30 gain benefits by lies and manipulations,  remaining in a sense invisible to others. The Just vs. the Unjust Life Glaucon then suggests a following thought  experiment: let’s say there were two magical   rings—one worn by a just person, the other by an  unjust one—and both gave their wearer the power   to act without consequences. It’s hard to believe  that anyone, no matter how virtuous, would resist   the temptation to abandon justice or avoid taking  what isn’t theirs. No one would stay honest or
            • 08:30 - 09:00 respect others' property if they could do whatever  they wanted without punishment. Some might say   this clearly shows that people are never just by  choice, but only because they’re forced to be. That is already a very strong point but Glaucon  doesn’t stop here. He then pushes it even further   and suggests to imagine two different people:  one fully just and one fully unjust. Imagine that   the first person manages to slip away with his  injustice and never get caught and, in fact, is   believed to be just in the society and is praised  for his good deeds. While the second person does
            • 09:00 - 09:30 only good actions and is accused of being unjust  and is punished and persecuted in the society much   like Plato’s teacher Socrates or Jesus Christ. Glaucon’s question is who will be happy and who   will be unhappy? This is probably the most fierce   illustration to show that justice is  not valuable in itself. After all,   how can we stand our ground if no one  believes in us and accuses us of wrongdoing?
            • 09:30 - 10:00 «They’ll say that a just person in  such circumstances will be whipped,   stretched on a rack, chained,  blinded with fire, and, at the end,   when he has suffered every kind of evil, he’ll be impaled, and will realize then that one shouldn’t   want to be just but to be believed to be just.» That’s where it gets clear that what we  truly want is not to be just but to have   a reputation for justice. Because this  reputation gives us all the benefits. A
            • 10:00 - 10:30 truly unjust person knows how the world  really works and doesn’t care about what   others think. He doesn’t want the image of  being unjust he wants to be unjust for real   while being perceived as the opposite. He’s smart  and strategic. Because people believe he’s just,   he gains power, marries into any family he  wants, arranges good marriages for his kids,   makes deals with anyone, and gets all the  benefits—without feeling bad about doing wrong. At this point, it seems impossible to  rehabilitate the concept of justice in
            • 10:30 - 11:00 the face of cynicism. Glaucon has convincingly  shown that justice is valued not for its own sake,   but as a useful instrument—and more importantly,  that it is the appearance of justice, rather than   justice itself, that holds real value. As long  as we avoid being caught in our injustices,   as long as no one sees the harm we commit,  we are regarded as successful. Justice seems   entirely discredited. Why be good when no one is  watching, and being bad brings rewards? Glaucon
            • 11:00 - 11:30 has forced us into a corner. And it is from  this corner that Socrates begins to push back. Socrates’s Response: Justice as Soul Harmony Socrates’s response to this  challenge is quite complex,   so it won’t be covered in detail in this video.  Instead, I’d like to focus on his strategy,   as it offers a general understanding of what he  aims to do in defending the concept of justice. He begins his defense by proposing that we  should first search for what justice is and   how it manifests. This seems reasonable, since  if we are to argue about something, we must first
            • 11:30 - 12:00 understand what it is, rather than merely discuss  how it benefits or harms us. To achieve this, he   examines how justice appears in society. His idea  is that because justice exists both in the state   and in the individual, it is better to investigate  justice in the state first. The reason is that   the state is larger, and therefore, as he puts  it, "there is more justice in the larger thing,   and it will be easier to learn what it is." Some philosophers have criticized this method,
            • 12:00 - 12:30 arguing that Socrates blurs the line between two  different kinds of justice—political justice in   the state and psychological justice in the  soul. They claim it's incoherent to assume   that what makes a society just is the same  as what makes an individual just. However,   others argue that his reasoning is not based  on mere analogy, but rather on a structural   similarity and deep interconnectedness between  the state and the individual. For Socrates,   the city and the soul reflect each other not  superficially, but in the way their internal
            • 12:30 - 13:00 parts are organized and how they function  together to produce harmony and justice.  This interconnectedness is precisely why  Socrates devotes so much attention to   education and cultural formation in The Republic.  He believes that the development of justice in the   soul is inseparable from the social and cultural  environment in which a person is raised. Children,   especially at a young age, mimic everything they  are exposed to and absorb models of behavior from
            • 13:00 - 13:30 their surroundings. Once these patterns take root  in early life, they become nearly impossible to   change later. Therefore, if we want individuals  to have a just organization of the psyche,   they must be exposed to just influences from  the beginning—and such influences can only   be reliably provided by a just state. For this reason, the state’s primary   role is to create conditions that foster  the growth of justice within individuals.
            • 13:30 - 14:00 All citizens must learn music to internalize  harmony and develop a sense of temperance,   especially in relation to food and sensual  pleasures. This helps keep their appetites in   check. Those naturally inclined toward courage  and physical strength—future warriors—must be   surrounded by stories of bravery and nobility  so that these qualities are solidified in their   characters. Philosophers, on the other hand,  must be immersed in wisdom and knowledge to   learn how to govern justly and pursue truth.  Through this comprehensive cultural shaping,
            • 14:00 - 14:30 the state transmits justice into  the souls of its inhabitants.  Yet the relationship works both ways: just  individuals also help sustain and reinforce the   justice of the state. When someone is raised in a  just environment and develops a harmonious psyche,   they are naturally inclined to act justly. These  just actions, in turn, influence others—especially   children—who observe and internalize these  patterns. For instance, a just warrior who   consistently demonstrates bravery and moderation  provides a living example for his children,
            • 14:30 - 15:00 who absorb this model of behavior and become  brave themselves, further reinforcing the   state’s justice. In this way, justice flows in  both directions—from the state into the soul,   and from the soul back into the state. Thus, Socrates shows us that justice   is not merely a social structure or an abstract  ideal, but a lived process of internalization and   externalization. It is shaped by our surroundings  and, once rooted in the soul, becomes a force that
            • 15:00 - 15:30 shapes society in return. His investigation is  grounded in careful observations of how cultural   influences affect psychological development and  how the state and individual, like mirror images,   co-create one another in the pursuit of justice. But this vision also serves a deeper purpose:   it provides a philosophical foundation for  why justice is not merely instrumental. If   the just soul is one in which reason rules  over spirit and appetite, and where each part
            • 15:30 - 16:00 performs its proper function in harmony, then  being just means being psychologically healthy,   internally ordered, and at peace. An unjust  person, by contrast, suffers from inner conflict,   with lower desires overpowering reason and leading  to a kind of self-inflicted tyranny. Socrates   ultimately argues that justice is valuable in  itself because it constitutes the well-being   of the soul. Just as physical health is  desirable not because of external praise but
            • 16:00 - 16:30 because it makes us function better and feel  whole, so too is justice something we should   pursue regardless of rewards or recognition. In this way, Socrates answers Glaucon not by   appealing to fear or reputation, but by showing  that the truly just life is the most fulfilling   one, even if it comes with suffering and  misunderstanding. Justice is not a mask   we wear to gain favor—it's a condition of  the soul we cultivate for its own sake,   because to live justly is to live well. What Would You Choose? So, what does it truly mean to be moral?  Is it simply about avoiding punishment and
            • 16:30 - 17:00 gaining approval, or is there something  deeper—a kind of harmony within the soul   that makes justice desirable in itself? «For  what will it profit a man if he gains the   whole world and forfeits his soul? Or what  shall a man give in return for his soul?»   Glaucon challenges us to confront our darkest  temptations and to ask whether we would still   act morally if no one could see us. But  Socrates invites us to look inward—to see   justice not as a burden, but as the very  structure of a healthy, fulfilled life.
            • 17:00 - 17:30 This is not an easy position to hold in a world  that often rewards appearances over substance.   But perhaps that’s what makes it so powerful.  When we choose to act justly even when no one   is watching—when we cultivate inner order rather  than chase external praise—we are choosing to live   a life of meaning, not convenience. So, I leave you with this question:   If you had the ring of Gyges—if no one could see  what you did—would you still choose to be just?
            • 17:30 - 18:00 Let me know in the comments below what  your answer is—and why. Would you side   with Glaucon’s realism or Socrates’s idealism?  And if this made you think more deeply about   your own moral compass, consider subscribing  for more philosophical content like this.